Book Read Free

Revolution and the Republic

Page 59

by Jeremy Jennings


  historian and therefore was initially uncertain about both his subject matter and

  methods of investigation. The end product did not take a narrative form and it

  dispensed with the conventional chronology of events, focusing rather upon the

  prehistory of the Revolution and what Tocqueville saw as its long-term causes. A

  never-to-be completed sequel was to be devoted to the Revolution proper. The final

  text drew upon extensive archival work, for the most part carried out in Tours

  (where Tocqueville was again in need of a period of convalescence), and it was here

  that he became convinced that the centralized administrative machinery associated

  with Napoleon was ‘purely the old regime preserved’.214 Tocqueville also made an

  extended trip to Germany in 1854 in search of still-existing feudal traditions

  analogous to those of pre-1789 France. In addition, he read memoirs of the period

  and consulted diplomatic documents.

  Tocqueville’s argument also built upon insights developed in two earlier texts: an

  essay detailing the social and political condition of France prior to 1789 published

  in John Stuart Mill’s London and Westminster Review in 1836215 and the reception

  speech he made before the Académie Française in April 1842.216 In the first,

  Tocqueville described a France that was increasingly homogeneous and character-

  ized by social equality and one where the central power of the State was stronger

  than anywhere else in the world. The Revolution, he argued, had only served to

  augment the equality of conditions and further to strengthen state power. In the

  second, and despite the formality of the occasion, Tocqueville castigated Napoleon

  for creating ‘the most perfected despotism’, commenting that ‘the eighteenth

  century and the Revolution, at the same time that they introduced new elements

  of liberty into the world, secretly sowed in the new society dangerous seeds from

  which absolute power could grow’.217

  The result of this long and arduous process of deliberation and research was a

  work divided clearly into three sections and held together by an argument that was

  deceptively simple. That argument was succinctly set out in the Foreword and then

  developed in book 1. The opening lines of the second paragraph read as follows: ‘in

  213 Alexis de Tocqueville, Œuvres complètes, viii/3. Correspondance d’Alexis de Tocqueville et de

  Gustave de Beaumont (1967), 370, 372–3, 379, 384.

  214 See Gannett, Tocqueville Unveiled, 79–98. Tocqueville first observed that the French system of

  administrative centralization was not born with the French Revolution but only perfected by it as early

  as 1835: see Œuvres complètes, i/1. De la Démocratie en Amérique (1961), 447.

  215 Alexis de Tocqueville, ‘Political and Social Condition of France’, London and Westminster

  Review, 8 (Apr. 1836), 137–69. See also ‘État social et politique de France avant et depuis 1789’, in

  Œuvres complètes, ii/1. L’Ancien Régime et la Révolution (1952), 31–66.

  216 ‘Discours de M. de Tocqueville prononcé dans la séance publique du 21 avril 1842 en venant

  prendre séance à la place de M. le Comte de Cessac’’, in Œuvres complètes, xvi. Mélanges (1989),

  251–69.

  217 Ibid. 259.

  278

  History, Revolution, and Terror

  1789 the French made the greatest effort ever undertaken by any people to break

  with their past and to put an abyss between what they had been and what they

  wished to become. To this end, they took all manner of precautions to bring

  nothing of the past into the new order.’218 Yet, Tocqueville continued, the French

  were far less successful in this than they had believed. Despite themselves and

  unintentionally, ‘they retained from the old regime most of the feelings, habits, and

  even ideas which helped them make the Revolution that destroyed it’.219 The new

  society was built upon the debris and wreckage of the past. From this Tocqueville

  drew two conclusions. The first was that properly to understand the Revolution one

  had to interrogate a France that no longer existed. The second was that no

  fundamental break had taken place in 1789. What the Revolution destroyed was

  everything in the old order that derived from aristocratic and feudal institutions but

  beneath the seemingly chaotic surface a clear pattern of continuity could be

  discerned. ‘I will show’, Tocqueville wrote, ‘how a stronger government, much

  more absolute than that which the Revolution had overthrown, arose and concen-

  trated all power in itself, suppressed all freedoms so dearly bought, and put vain

  images in their place.’220

  The central empirical claim underpinning this interpretation of the Revolution

  was sketched in book 2 and was summarized by Tocqueville in the title he gave to

  one of its chapters: ‘How Administrative Centralization is an Institution of the

  Ancien Régime and not the Work of either the Revolution or the Empire, as is

  said’.221 In brief, Tocqueville’s argument was that, despite appearances of diversity

  and confusion to the contrary, it had been the French monarchy that had built a

  vast centralized bureaucracy with tentacles spreading throughout the kingdom and

  intruding into all aspects of daily life. In summary, Tocqueville wrote, there existed

  ‘a single body, located at the centre of the kingdom, which regulated public

  administration throughout the entire country; the same minister directing almost

  all internal affairs; in each province, a single official in charge of all the details; no

  secondary administrative bodies or bodies able to act without prior authorization to

  do so; exceptional courts which judged matters relating to the administration and

  its officers’.222 If its procedures were less regular and its machinery less efficient

  than what now existed, nothing of importance had since been added or subtracted

  from it. ‘It has been sufficient’, Tocqueville commented, ‘to pull down all that had

  been erected around it for it to appear as we now see it.’223

  The consequences for the condition of French society, according to Tocqueville,

  had been profound. Government exercised a quasi-paternal tutelage over the

  population. Municipal government had declined into petty oligarchy. The admin-

  istration resented all independent bodies and distrusted any display of initiative

  from private citizens. Paris had achieved absolute predominance over the country.

  More troubling still were the pathologies that had arisen from the vast gulf existing

  between the government and individual citizen. Having taken the place of divine

  218 Œuvres complètes, ii/1. L’Ancien Régime et la Révolution, 69.

  219 Ibid.

  220 Ibid. 72.

  221 Ibid. 107.

  222 Ibid. 127.

  223 Ibid.

  History, Revolution, and Terror

  279

  providence, it was but natural that everyone should turn to government when in

  need. ‘No one imagined’, Tocqueville argued, ‘that an important matter could be

  brought to a successful conclusion without the intervention of the State.’224 If the

  eradication of local and regional differences and of distinctions between classes

  meant that individuals more and more resembled each other, the process of


  centralization also ensured that they were more than ever separated from one

  another. People were indifferent to the fate of others and mutual suspicion reigned.

  What mattered most were the petty privileges and prerogatives marking them out,

  however flimsily, from their rivals. But, Tocqueville observed, ‘everyone was ready

  to merge into the same mass, provided that no one remained apart and no one rose

  above the common level’.225 When, at last, they had come together in 1789 their

  first thought was to tear each other apart.

  The final component of this noxious state of mind was the existence of an ‘unusual

  kind of freedom’. It would be wrong to believe, Tocqueville commented, that the

  ancien régime was a time of ‘servility and subservience’. The ‘art’ of silencing dissent

  was far less perfected than it had later become. To that extent there was more freedom

  than now existed—the soul was kept free—but ‘it was a kind of freedom that was

  irregular and intermittent, always constrained within the limits of a class, always

  linked to the idea of exception and privilege’.226 If it served a function in preparing

  the French to overthrow despotism, ‘it perhaps made them less suited than any

  other people to establish in its place the free and peaceable empire of law’.227 When

  taken together, Tocqueville seemed to suggest, the combined weight of these factors

  was such as to indicate that the outcome of the Revolution was predetermined.

  We should not be surprised, he speculated, by the ease with which centralization had

  been re-established at the beginning of the nineteenth century: ‘The men of 89

  had toppled the building but its foundations had remained in the very souls of its

  destroyers and upon these foundations it was possible to raise it up anew and to build

  it more solidly than ever before.’228

  All that remained to be done was to assess the immediate causes and precise

  character of the Revolution. Here Tocqueville returned his readers to one of the

  original questions that had informed analyses of the Revolution: what had been the

  role played by men of letters? In Tocqueville’s opinion, it had been a very signifi-

  cant one. Despite their disagreements, Tocqueville argued, the political pro-

  grammes of the writers of the eighteenth century all agreed on the need to

  replace the old order with one grounded upon a set of simple and general principles

  derived from reason and natural law. Given the injustice and absurdities of the

  world they saw around them, Tocqueville conceded, it could hardly have been

  otherwise. However, Tocqueville next postulated that this predilection for abstract

  theories and generalizations was a reflection of their social and political marginality.

  They simply lacked experience of the real world and, as a consequence, failed to

  appreciate the obstacles that stood in the way of even the most laudable and

  seemingly straightforward reforms. The same ignorance of the everyday realities

  224 Ibid. 135.

  225 Ibid. 158.

  226 Ibid. 176.

  227 Ibid. 177.

  228 Ibid. 138.

  280

  History, Revolution, and Terror

  of politics among the French in general provided a wider public receptive to these

  ideas, with the result that the entire nation ended up adopting the attitudes and

  tastes of the men of letters. ‘Little by little’, Tocqueville observed, ‘there was built

  up an imaginary society in which everything appeared simple and coordinated,

  uniform, equitable and in accordance with reason.’229 Moreover, it was precisely

  this fondness for abstract theory and ingenious preconceived institutions that had

  inspired the Revolution to believe that society could be reordered from top to

  bottom following the rules of logic.

  To this ‘frightening sight’ needed to be added two further dimensions of the

  thinking of the men of letters. The first was the widespread and virulent anti-

  religious sentiment that came to prevail in France. Nowhere else had irreligion

  become such ‘a general, ardent, intolerant, and oppressive passion’.230 To those

  who deified reason an institution for which tradition was fundamental could only

  be worthy of contempt. In Tocqueville’s opinion, ‘the universal discredit’ suffered

  by religion was to shape the character of the Revolution in a decisive and prepon-

  derant way. The result of overthrowing religious institutions and government at the

  same time, Tocqueville argued, was that ‘the human mind entirely lost its direction;

  it no longer knew what to hold on to nor where to stop’.231 As a consequence, a

  new species of revolutionary appeared who took audacity to the point of madness

  and, lacking scruples, hesitated before no innovation. These ‘new beings’, Tocque-

  ville commented, were not ‘ephemeral creations of the moment’: they had perpe-

  tuated themselves and were still with us.

  Tocqueville’s next allegation was that the men of letters had taught the French to

  prize reform before freedom. This claim rested upon the unusual argument that the

  most substantial reforms of the Revolution had been announced in the writings of

  the physiocrats. Why Tocqueville sought to argue this becomes clear when we see

  that, in his view, the physiocrats were not only completely contemptuous of the

  past but were also of the opinion that ‘it was not a question of destroying absolute

  power but of converting it’ to a more appropriate use.232 It was the function of the

  State to reform and transform both society and the nation and to achieve that end

  they set little store upon political liberty. For that reason, the French came to

  embrace a set of ideas that were antithetical to free institutions such that, when at

  last a love of freedom awoke among them, they found that they had accepted ‘as an

  ideal society a people without any other aristocracy than that of public function-

  aries, with a single and all-powerful administration directing affairs of State and

  acting as the guardian of all individuals’.233 It was this attempt to superimpose

  liberty upon the institutions of a servile state, Tocqueville concluded, that ex-

  plained why, for the last sixty years, so many vain attempts to establish free

  government had been followed by disastrous revolutions. Fatigued, the French

  were now content to live as equals.

  229 Œuvres complètes, ii/1. L’Ancien Régime et la Révolution, 199.

  230 Ibid. 202.

  231 Ibid. 208.

  232 Ibid. 212.

  233 Ibid. 216.

  History, Revolution, and Terror

  281

  How, finally, were these ideas turned into action? Tocqueville highlighted three

  factors. First, and contrary to what had been imagined, the very prosperity of Louis

  XVI’s reign hastened revolution by raising expectations. Second, well-intentioned

  and disinterested efforts to improve the welfare of the people only served to fuel their

  resentment and increase their desires. Third, the monarchy itself employed practices

  that were ‘hostile to the individual, contrary to private rights, and friendly to

  violence’.234 ‘The ancien régime’, Tocqueville commented, ‘provided the Revolution

  with many of its methods: the latter only added the savagery of its spirit.’235
When,

  therefore, administrative reform was introduced, this set in motion a process that led

  to ‘the greatest upheaval and the most frightening confusion there ever was’.236

  Thus the Revolution was inevitable and so, Tocqueville suggested, was the contrast

  between theory and practice, good intentions and violent acts, which marked its

  course. However, what Tocqueville chose to highlight by way of conclusion was that

  the eighteenth century had given rise to two ruling passions. The first, with deeper

  roots and of longer standing, was an intense hatred of inequality. The second, of more

  recent origin, was a zeal for liberty. In 1789, these two passions coalesced, the French

  believing that they could be equal in their freedom. Free institutions existed alongside

  democratic institutions, and ‘centralization fell with absolute government’.237 Yet,

  with the passing of the ‘vigorous generation’ that had begun the Revolution, the love

  of liberty subsided amidst ‘anarchy and popular dictatorship’ and the taste for equality

  prevailed. And so ‘from the very bowels of a nation that had just overthrown the

  monarchy suddenly emerged a power more extensive, more detailed, and more

  absolute than that exercised by any of our kings’.238 From this point onwards,

  Tocqueville concluded, the French had limited themselves to ‘placing the head of

  Liberty upon a servile body’.239

  Contained within L’Ancien Régime et la Révolution was a passionate plea for

  individual liberty as an end in itself. Yet this very same book served as an explana-

  tion of the failure of liberty to secure a solid foundation and sustained existence in

  France. Seen thus, the anomaly in Tocqueville’s account was the moment of

  ‘greatness’ and ‘virility’, the ‘time of immortal memory’ as he described it, when

  the call for liberty, long submerged beneath despotism, all-too-briefly made its

  voice heard above the clamour for vengeance. It was a moment that almost defied

  explanation, such was the weight that Tocqueville attributed to the prevailing

  tradition of centralization and its eradication of countervailing trends. This perhaps

  explains the peculiar passage at the very end of the book where Tocqueville spoke of

  the unique character of the French people. No nation was so full of contrasts, so

 

‹ Prev