Book Read Free

Revolution and the Republic

Page 69

by Jeremy Jennings


  provided the first significant sign of Catholic revival.149 As he was later to comment

  in his memoirs:

  It was amid the remains of our temples that I published Le Génie du Christianisme.

  The faithful felt themselves saved; there was then a need for a faith, a hunger for

  religious consolation, which sprang from the denial of these consolations over many

  years. . . . People were rushing into the house of God in the same way as they entered a

  doctor’s at the outbreak of a contagious disease. The victims of our troubles (and how many

  they were) sought salvation at the altar, like the shipwrecked clinging to a rock for safety.

  ‘The idea of God and the immortality of the soul’, he continued, ‘reclaimed their

  dominion.’150 As a work of theology, the quality of Chateaubriand’s text may be

  judged by his concluding argument. ‘Christianity is perfect; men are imperfect.

  A perfect outcome cannot follow from an imperfect principle. Therefore Christian-

  ity does not come from men. If it does not come from men, it can only come from

  God. If it comes from God, men can only know it by revelation. Therefore

  146 See Ruth Harris, Lourdes: Body and Spirit in the Secular Age (London, 1999).

  147 See Raymond A. Jones, ‘Monument as Ex-Voto, Monument as Historiography: The Basilica of

  Sacré-Cœur’, French Historical Studies, 18 (1993), 482–502.

  148 See Jacqueline Lalouette, La République anticléricale (2002), 301–412.

  149 See James F. McMillan, ‘Catholic Christianity in France from Restoration to the Separation of

  Church and State, 1815–1905’, in Sheridan Gilley and Brian Stanley (eds.), The Cambridge History of

  Christianity, viii. World Christianities c.1815–c.1914 (Cambridge, 2006), 219.

  150 Chateaubriand, Mémoires d’outre-tombe (1973), i. 527–9.

  Religion, Enlightenment, and Reaction

  325

  Christianity is a revealed religion.’151 Arguments of a similar style and dubious

  quality were used to sustain the accuracy of biblical chronology. These defects,

  however, did little to diminish the rapture induced among its readers.

  Subtitled ‘The Beauties of the Christian Religion’, Chateaubriand’s text started

  from the premise that there was nothing beautiful, sweet, or great in the world that

  was not also mysterious and from this it set out to prove that,

  of all religions, the Christian religion is the most poetic, the most humane, the most

  favourable to liberty and to the arts and literature . . . that there is nothing more divine

  than its morality, nothing more attractive and splendid than its tenets, its doctrines and

  its forms of worship; that it encourages genius, refines taste, develops the virtuous

  passions, imparts vigour to thought, presents noble forms to the writer and perfect

  models to the artist.152

  The ambition, in other words, was to refute all those from Voltaire onwards who

  had claimed incorrectly that Christianity was born out of barbarism and that it held

  men in a condition of savagery, darkness, and slavery; and thus to show the

  contribution of Christianity to everything that was most sublime, inspiring, and

  valuable in Western civilization. This Chateaubriand achieved with both eloquence

  and erudition. Having safely navigated around the mysteries and sacraments of

  Christian doctrine, the text warmed to its task, exploring first ‘the Poetry of

  Christianity’ and then ‘Fine Arts and Literature’. Sculpture, drama, sacred music,

  painting, and the Gothic cathedrals were all deployed inter alia to provide what

  amounted to a Christian apologetic as aesthetics. In similar vein, the concluding

  section evoked the beauties of the liturgy and the emotional power of the church

  bell and country cemetery. Chateaubriand, then, appealed not to the reason of his

  readers but to their hearts, to their feelings, and to their deepest sensibilities.

  Not everyone was convinced or swayed—least of all, the house journal of the

  Idéologues, the Décade philosophique, where it was severely treated by Pierre-Louis

  Ginguené as a text defending counter-revolution and superstition153—but its

  influence among literary circles and the broader public spread far and wide and

  did so for much of the first half of the nineteenth century. Above all, Chateaubriand

  gave Catholics cause to be proud of their faith, restoring its credibility and prestige,

  and in so doing he revealed the spiritual poverty and sterility of the atheism

  bequeathed by the eighteenth century. The latter, he wrote, offered us only

  suffering, death, the coffin, and nothingness.154

  In Chateaubriand’s hands, Catholicism not only became attractive but almost

  fashionable. His evocative and rich prose struck a chord with a France disillusioned

  by the violence and chaos of the Revolution and a country grown sceptical of the

  claims of reason. The mood had changed and, capturing the moment, Chateaubri-

  and conjured up the romance of the past and the possibilities of a new age of

  imagination and sentiment. The publication of Le Génie du Christianisme, Barbey

  d’Aurevilly was to write in 1851, ‘had something of the supernatural and the astral

  151 Chateaubriand, Le Génie du Christianisme (1966), ii. 256.

  152 Ibid. i. 57.

  153 See Kitchin, Un journal ‘philosophique’, 174–7.

  154 Ibid. 214.

  326

  Religion, Enlightenment, and Reaction

  about it’.155 Yet Chateaubriand’s poignant apology for Christianity was not the

  only manifestation of a resurgent Catholicism present at the time. By its side was to

  be found a darker and more apocalyptic expression of Catholic faith and one which,

  in its total opposition to the Enlightenment and all its supposed ills, set itself

  resolutely against the moral decay of post-revolutionary society.

  Antoine Compagnon has described some of the essential features of this mental-

  ity in a work appropriately entitled Les antimodernes.156 The discourse of antimo-

  dernity, he argues, was counter-revolutionary, against the philosophes, pessimistic

  about the possibilities of man and society, believed in one version or other of the

  doctrine of original sin, embraced an aesthetics of the sublime, and, last but not

  least, adopted a tone of vituperation and vengeance. The specific characteristics of

  this frame of mind typical of the early nineteenth century have likewise been

  sketched by Darrin McMahon.157 After 1800, McMahon records, the defenders

  of the philosophes were subject to a ‘powerful new onslaught’ and this from authors

  who had but recently been forced ‘to conduct their campaigns in exile, in hiding,

  and in fear of revolutionary reprisals’.158 For these writers, Christianity was not

  merely socially necessary and useful but also true. It was a repository of certainty in

  a world of scepticism and doubt. Articles in such periodicals as the Journal des débats

  and the Mercure argued against toleration and for the rigorous censorship of

  religious opinion. In similar vein, anti-philosophe polemic praised the patriarchal

  family and denounced divorce, believing that parricide went hand in hand with

  regicide. History, on this view, showed the limits to human perfection and

  demonstrated the need for strong social and political institutions to control the

  wayward be
haviour of ordinary mortals. Prejudice, custom, and tradition were to

  be valued, as were France’s ancient monarchy and institutions. Finally, the anti-

  philosophes were in near-unanimous agreement that France had been at its greatest,

  most polished, and most devout, under the reign of Louis XIV and that since then

  the country had passed ‘into utter depravity’.159 The political agenda spawned by

  such tirades against the present was clear enough. France, these ‘prophets of the

  past’ believed,160 would not make a return to social harmony and order until such

  time as religious orthodoxy had been re-established and the unity of throne and

  altar had been restored.

  It would be wrong to overstate the level of doctrinal unity that existed among this

  diverse and, for the most part, little-known group of writers. Theological divisions

  in particular were never far from the surface and it would be a mistake to think in

  terms of an organized movement or party galvanized around an exclusive opposi-

  tion to the siècle des lumières. Likewise, many of the strident criticisms of the

  corrosive and contagious effects of the philosophic spirit that were articulated in

  155 Jules Barbey d’Aurevilly, Les Prophètes du passé (1860), 110.

  156 Compagnon, Les Antimodernes de Joseph de Maistre à Roland Barthes (2005).

  157 Darrin M. McMahon, Enemies of the Enlightenment: The French Counter-Enlightenment and the

  Making of Modernity (Oxford, 2001), 122–52.

  158 Ibid. 122–3.

  159 Ibid. 147.

  160 This is the title of the work by Barbey d’Aurevilly cited above.

  Religion, Enlightenment, and Reaction

  327

  the wake of the Revolution were in circulation (sometimes albeit in embryonic

  form) before 1789. However, the Revolution itself, holding aloft the very possibi-

  lity of the annihilation of the Catholic religion, served to radicalize these earlier

  pronouncements and to give them greater urgency and force. To that extent, the

  Revolution appeared to validate the dire warnings of disaster that the defenders

  of the Church had made repeatedly under the ancien régime. After the Revolu-

  tion, therefore, with the worst fears of anti-philosophe opinion realized, the battle

  was truly enjoined. In the previous chapter we saw one example of this bitter

  enmity: the philosophes stood accused of leading a revolutionary conspiracy to

  destroy both Christianity and the monarchy. Philosophie and the philosophes were

  now to be subjected to relentless and destructive criticism before the jury of public

  opinion that they themselves had worked to create. Central to this was an attempted

  refutation of everything that the Enlightenment was taken to stand for.

  We have already had reason to examine the ideas of Joseph de Maistre. He has

  featured as an opponent of the doctrine of rights, as an acerbic critic of Rousseau

  and of social contract theory, and as an advocate of the satanic quality of the

  Revolution. Now he is to figure as the staunch defender of religion, papal authority,

  and the public executioner.161 Maistre, we might recall, was firmly of the opinion

  that it was the philosophers of the Enlightenment who had produced the revolu-

  tionary monster that had devastated France and Europe. In addition to this, he had

  a series of substantive objections to the philosophisme of his eighteenth-century

  enemy.162 These objections informed all his mature writings and took three

  primary forms. First, Maistre rejected what he took to be the Enlightenment’s

  theory of knowledge. In particular, he rejected the view that there were no such

  things as innate ideas. Next, he dismissed the paradigmatic status accorded to

  natural science. Finally, he denounced (and ridiculed) the Enlightenment’s enthu-

  siasm for a priori and abstract reasoning. Taken together, they amounted to one

  overall criticism: the Enlightenment displayed a misplaced pride and trust in the

  power of man’s unaided intellect. ‘Philosophy’, Maistre countered, ‘is nothing but

  human reason acting alone, and human reason reduced to its own resources is

  nothing but a brute whose power is restricted to destroying.’163 It amounted, he

  wrote in May 1809, to an ‘insurrection against God’.164 Elsewhere, in the later Les

  Soirées de Saint-Petersbourg, he spoke of philosophy as ‘theophobia’ and as ‘a system

  of practical atheism’.165 In his view, we were witnessing a fight to the death

  between Christianity and the cult of philosophy.

  161 See Jesse Goldhammer, ‘Joseph de Maistre and the Politics of Conservative Regeneration’, The

  Headless Republic: Sacrificial Violence in Modern French Thought (Ithaca, NY, and London, 2005),

  71–111.

  162 When Maistre spoke of philosophisme rather than philosophie, he was intentionally designating a

  form of false philosophy that relied upon the misuse of reason. The term was very current in the latter

  half of the 18th cent.

  163 De la Souveraineté du peuple (1992), 132–3.

  164 ‘Essai sur le Principe générateur des constitutions politiques et des autres institutions humaines’,

  in Pierre Glaudes (ed.), Joseph de Maistre: Œuvres (2007), 399.

  165 ‘Les Soirées de Saint-Petersbourg ou Entretiens sur le gouvernement temporal de la Providence’,

  ibid. 59.

  328

  Religion, Enlightenment, and Reaction

  Maistre did not read Locke’s Essay on the Human Understanding until 1806.166

  Having read it, he quickly concluded that ‘contempt for Locke is the beginning of

  wisdom’.167 His philosophy was as false as it was dangerous. Maistre’s argument

  against Locke and Lockean epistemology may be briefly summarized as follows.168

  Locke was a superficial and mediocre thinker. He was ‘incapacity demonstrated’.

  His work was frequently characterized by ‘grossness’ of expression, as, for example,

  when he described the memory as a box where ideas were stored until needed or the

  human intellect as a dark room with several windows to let in the light.169 Most of

  all, what Locke said was either straightforwardly banal or plain wrong. This,

  Maistre maintained, was true of Locke’s central proposition: that all our ideas

  came from either the senses or from reflection. ‘Torturing the truth’, Maistre

  argued, Locke was forced to accept that ‘general ideas’ were ‘inventions or CREA-

  TURES of the human mind’, for ‘according to the doctrine of this great philoso-

  pher, man makes general ideas with simple ideas, just as he makes boats with

  planks’.170 The fallacy in Locke’s argument was all too evident. Every idea, Maistre

  argued, that did not originate either in the mind’s interaction with external objects

  or the consideration of itself by the mind must derive from the substance of the

  mind. From this, Maistre declared jubilantly, it followed that ‘there are ideas that

  are innate and prior to all experience’.171 Consequently, Locke’s entire argument

  stood exposed as ‘splendid nonsense’.

  Maistre’s own references to innate ideas displayed a significant (and perhaps

  understandable) element of uncertainty and hesitation. ‘Whether universal ideas

  are innate in us, or whether we derive them from God, or whatever you like’,

  Maistre argued defensively, ‘is not important.’172 What matt
ered was that we

  recognized that Locke’s epistemology contained ‘the gravest and vilest of errors’.

  To deny the existence of innate ideas was not only to deny the spiritual essence of

  man but also to deny the very possibility of morality. Man, Maistre insisted, carried

  within him certain common moral opinions or eternal verities. ‘I ought to do it’ was,

  Maistre contended, an ‘innate idea whose nature is independent of every error of

  application’. If this assumption were not accepted, he concluded, it would be

  impossible to conceive of ‘the unity of the human species’.173

  Having thus dismissed Locke’s theory of knowledge and pointed out its dangers

  when placed in the hands of its ‘venomous’ French adherents, Maistre was next in a

  position to challenge what he saw as the false and mistaken conception of science so

  dear to the eighteenth century. Upon this occasion his ire was directed against yet

  another illustrious exemplar of English empiricism: Francis Bacon. The Examen de

  la Philosophie de Bacon ou l’on traite différentes questions de la philosophie rationnelle

  was written between 1814 and 1816 (although not published until 1836) and

  followed the publication of Bacon’s complete works in French at the turn of the

  166 See Richard A. Lebrun, ‘Maistrian Epistemology’, in Lebrun (ed.), Maistre Studies (Lanham,

  Md., 1988), 209. See also E. D. Watt, ‘“Locked In”: De Maistre’s Critique of French Lockeanism’,

  Journal of the History of Ideas, 32 (1971), 129–32.

  167 Maistre, ‘Les Soirées de Saint-Petersbourg’, 640.

  168 Ibid. 601–48.

  169 Ibid. 612.

  170 Ibid. 623.

  171 Ibid. 624.

  172 Ibid. 511.

  173 Ibid. 626–7.

  Religion, Enlightenment, and Reaction

  329

  century. It amounted to a 700-page, two-volume refutation and dismissal of

  everything Bacon ever wrote or said.174 His philosophy, Maistre stated, was ‘a

  continuous aberration’. Bacon ‘was mistaken about logic, about metaphysics, about

  physics, about natural history, about astronomy, about mathematics, about chem-

  istry, about medicine and, finally, about everything relating to the vast area of

  natural philosophy on which he dared to speak’.175 Specifically, Maistre denied that

 

‹ Prev