Book Read Free

Revolution and the Republic

Page 97

by Jeremy Jennings


  refuse assent to a judgement whose legality appeared to them to be suspect, it is not

  because . . . they attribute to themselves any special privileges or any exclusive right of

  control over the question. It is rather that, being men, they seek to exercise their entire

  right as men and to keep before them a matter which concerns reason alone. It is true

  that they have shown themselves more jealous of this right than the rest of society; but

  this is simply because, as a result of their professional activities, they have it nearer to

  heart. Accustomed by the practice of scientific method to reserve their judgement

  when they are not fully aware of the facts, it is natural for them to give in less easily to

  the enthusiasms of the crowd or to the prestige of authority.108

  Thus, the ‘individualist’ who defended the rights of the individual was at the same

  time defending ‘the vital interests of society’ and, Durkheim continued, in no other

  country was this cause more ‘truly national’ than in France. To renounce it, he told

  his readers, would be ‘to renounce ourselves’, to ‘diminish ourselves in the eyes of

  the world’, to ‘commit real moral suicide’.109 It was, in other words, Brunetière

  who was speaking against the soul of France. To that extent, according to Dur-

  kheim, anti-Semitism in France, if not elsewhere, was ‘the consequence and

  symptom of a state of social malaise’.110

  Against Barrès stood Lucien Herr, librarian of the École Normale Supérieure and

  an Alsatian Protestant.111 Writing in the Dreyfusard La Revue blanche,112 he told

  Barrès that ‘your idea is that the French soul, French integrity, is today being

  insulted and compromised to the advantage of foreigners, by the infernal machina-

  tions of other foreigners, and aided by the complicity of second-rate intellectuals

  de-nationalized by a second-rate culture’.113 This, Herr believed, was nonsense.

  More tellingly, he also turned his fire against Barrès’s conception of France. ‘At the

  heart of your national patriotism’, he continued, ‘you would find not the old

  France . . . but a conquering, proud and brutal France, Napoleonic France, the

  jingoistic chauvinism of our large cities, the impassioned instinct for warlike glory,

  barbarous exaltation, hatred and the arrogance of force.’114 This, he made plain,

  was not his France. ‘The French soul’, Herr wrote, ‘has only been truly great and

  strong at those moments when it has been welcoming and generous’. Nor was it the

  107 Revue bleue, 8–9.

  108 Ibid.

  109 Ibid. 12.

  110 Dagan, Enquête, 59–63.

  111 See Charles Andler, Vie de Lucien Herr 1864–1926 (1932) and Robert Smith, ‘L’Atmosphère

  politique à l’École Normale Supérieure à la fin du XIXe siècle’, Revue d’histoire moderne et

  contemporaine, 20 (1973), 248–68.

  112 ‘A M. Maurice Barrès’, La Revue blanche, 15 (1898), 241–5.

  113 Ibid. 242.

  114 Ibid. 243.

  France, Intellectuals, and Engagement

  459

  France of the ‘young people’ who had rallied to the Dreyfusard cause. They, like

  Barrès himself, did not claim to possess the whole truth but ‘they have within

  themselves something which is absolute: the faith in a human ideal’.115

  I I

  One of the common meeting places of these young people was the tiny bookshop

  and office of Charles Péguy, located in the heart of Paris’s Latin Quarter in the rue

  Cujas.116 It was here that, with passionate intensity, they followed the dramatic

  course of events and where, on the rock of the Dreyfus Affair, their friendships were

  ultimately to be broken. Quickly disillusioned, in their eyes the triumph of the

  Dreyfusard cause had been sullied by the actions of unscrupulous politicians intent

  upon reaping their own personal reward and upon punishing both the Roman

  Catholic Church and the army for their misdemeanours. This mood of disenchant-

  ment was captured well by Georges Sorel, a weekly visitor to Péguy’s bookshop, in

  La Révolution dreyfusienne. Published in 1908, it was undoubtedly Sorel’s worst

  book, but its clear message was that the policies of the victorious republicans––

  especially the anticlerical Émile Combes––had put an end ‘to the passable func-

  tioning of the parliamentary regime’ and had brought about the ascendancy of what

  he dubbed ‘a philosophy of hypocritical cowardice’. Few were spared from Sorel’s

  venomous and scornful bile. Émile Zola, he wrote, ‘was the representative example

  of the buffoonery of the time . . . He can be compared to a clown parading before a

  fairground stall.’117

  By Sorel’s own admission, his volume caused something of ‘a scandal’118 but this

  was as nothing compared to the controversy evoked by Daniel Halévy’s ‘Apologie

  pour notre passé’.119 The ‘our past’ of the title was the past of a small group of

  young men (which included future socialist prime minister Léon Blum and critic

  Julien Benda)120 for whom the Dreyfus Affair had acted to define them as human

  beings. According to Halévy’s account, they had had no opinions, occupations, or

  friendships prior to the Affair but within a short space of time all (and more, their

  hatreds) were decided upon. ‘A single and redoubtable crisis’, Halévy wrote, ‘took

  hold of us and marked us.’121 He and his friends, Halévy recalled, became involved

  in the Dreyfusard cause not just to save an innocent man but to save ‘an innocent

  115 Ibid. 244.

  116 See Daniel Halévy, Charles Péguy and Les Cahiers de la Quinzaine (London, 1946). See Géraldi

  Leroy, Péguy: Entre l’ordre et la révolution (1981) and Alain Finkielkraut, Le Mécontemporain: Péguy,

  lecteur du monde moderne (1991).

  117 La Révolution dreyfusienne (1908), 35.

  118 ‘Lettres de Georges Sorel à Edouard Berth: Deuxième Partie: 1909–1910’, Cahiers Georges Sorel,

  4 (1986), 86.

  119 Daniel Halévy, ‘Apologie pour notre passé’, Cahiers de la quinzaine, 10th cahier of the 11th series,

  1910. See Pierre Guiral, ‘Daniel Halévy, esquisse d’un itinéraire’, Contrepoint, 20 (1976), 79–95.

  120 Both were to write at length about this experience: see Léon Blum, Souvenirs sur l’Affaire (1935)

  and Julien Benda, La Jeunesse d’un clerc (1936).

  121 Halévy, ‘Apologie pour notre passé’, 8.

  460

  France, Intellectuals, and Engagement

  France’ whose honour was being betrayed by ‘a small group of men poisoned by

  fear, by hate’. At issue, then, had been ‘the salvation of the French spirit’.122 Yet,

  from within their own number and as a result of their own efforts, a ‘demagogic

  bloc’ had emerged and had taken control of the State.

  The potency of Halévy’s text lies in the way it combined reflection and memory

  to turn a recent event into history––‘our memories are already our masters’, he

  wrote123––but if it remains known today it is largely because it elicited one of

  Charles Péguy’s greatest works, Notre Jeunesse, published in 1910.124 Here was a

  text that pushed eloquence and lyricism to the point where the recovery of history

  played little part. ‘I am shocked’, Sorel wrote to Halévy, ‘to see the extent to which


  Péguy sacrifices reality (which does not seem to interest him at all) to the require-

  ments of oratorical development.’125 Pèguy himself did not see it that way. ‘My

  past’, he wrote, ‘has no need of apology . . . I have no need of being defended.’126

  Nor did he have the intention of writing ‘the memoirs of a weakling, of a penitent’.

  Specifically, he did not recognize himself as the ‘downtrodden dog’ of Halévy’s

  account. He had been mistaken and he had been fooled but he had not been

  beaten. Nor, he asserted, had he been a victim of an ‘illusion of youth’. Rather the

  defence of Dreyfus––a man, Péguy believed, who would not have died for his own

  cause––had been something akin to a religion. A single crime, a single injustice, had

  been sufficient to break the social compact and thus theirs had been a struggle to

  restore ‘the historic honour of our people, the entire historic honour of our entire

  race, the honour of our ancestors, the honour of our children’. ‘Deep down’, he

  wrote, ‘we were men concerned with eternal salvation and our adversaries with

  temporal salvation. That is the true, the real division of the Dreyfus Affair.’127

  Halévy’s mistake had been to presume that it was the politicians who represented

  the Dreyfusard movement and therefore he had forgotten the fervour and ardour

  that had inspired their own original commitment.

  Where did what Halévy later described as Péguy’s ‘glorious memory of the event’

  lead him?128 First, he placed Bernard Lazare at the centre of his account. A

  ‘prophet’ and ‘one of the great names of the modern age’, his reward had been

  solitude and to be forgotten.129 Next, to explain the decline of the Dreyfusard

  movement into careerism and cynicism he forged his famous distinction between

  mystique and politique. As Péguy expressed it, one died for a mystique but one lived

  off a politique: the first was principled; the second was self-interested. Politique was

  the devouring of the mystique that gave the movement its original force. Moreover,

  in Péguy’s view, all movements began as mystiques and ended as politiques.130

  Péguy, therefore, believed that he and his friends had been ‘the mystics’; that

  they had always been ‘the heart and the centre’ of the Dreyfusard cause; and that, if

  122 Halévy, ‘Apologie pour notre passé’, 38–9.

  123 Ibid. 8.

  124 See Péguy, Notre Jeunesse, in Œuvres en prose, 1909–1914 (1961), 501–655.

  125 ‘Lettres de Georges Sorel à Daniel Halévy’, Mil Neuf Cent, 12 (1994), 184.

  126 Péguy, Notre Jeunesse, 563.

  127 Ibid. 648.

  128 Halévy, Charles Péguy, 110.

  129 Péguy, Notre Jeunesse, 551–3.

  130 Ibid. 518.

  France, Intellectuals, and Engagement

  461

  their enemies had spoken the language of raison d’état, their concern had been that

  ‘France should not fall into a state of mortal sin’.131

  This was only the springboard for a broader digression about the condition

  of France. On Péguy’s account, the Dreyfusard mystique had been inspired by

  the virtues of justice, charity, courage, perseverance, and self-sacrifice. These

  virtues, he wanted to argue, were not simply ‘republican’ virtues: they were also

  Christian virtues. The Dreyfusard movement, in other words, encompassed both

  the republican and Christian mystiques. Péguy’s simple point here was that the

  Catholic Church, instead of opposing the Dreyfusard cause, should have recog-

  nized its religious character. His broader point was that both mystiques were part

  of what he constantly referred to as l’ancienne France. It was for this reason that

  Péguy refused to see ‘the 1st January 1789 (Paris time)’ as the great divide in French

  history.

  In this Péguy was fortified by a provincial and rural education in which, as he

  recounted, his schoolmasters and priests, for all their ‘metaphysical’ differences, had

  taught the same morality and the same discipline, had taught the virtues of ‘the

  French race’. Yet his argument was that this France was coming to an end. The

  Dreyfus Affair, he believed, represented the ‘last operation of the republican

  mystique’. This was so because France was entering a period of ‘demystification’.

  To that extent, ‘de-republicanization’ went hand in hand with ‘de-Christianization’.

  The same ‘sterility’ was afflicting ‘the city of men and the city of God’. For the first

  time we were living in a world ‘opposed to all culture’.132

  So, for Péguy, the dividing line came not in 1789 but ‘around 1881’.133 Up to

  that moment the Republic had been a ‘restoration’ (it had, in actual fact, been a

  republic of the notables, a republic without republicans) but after this, according

  to Péguy, it lapsed into ‘cæsarism’ and demagogy. Worse still, the Republic had

  fallen under ‘the domination of the intellectual party’.134 In Notre Jeunesse, and in

  many other texts,135 Péguy’s denunciation of this ‘tyranny’ knew almost no

  bounds. It was a system of oppression, of corruption, of depravity, of lying that,

  for over thirty years, had tried to overthrow God, the Church, France, the army,

  morality, and the law. The unfortunate Jaurès was singled out for particular

  condemnation and reproach as the ‘bourgeois intellectual’ who had subverted

  and corrupted the workers’ movement. Péguy, in short, was perhaps the first to

  suspect that the intellectuals had betrayed their calling, and his bitterness was all

  the greater for the lofty conception he had had of their almost-sacred role. The

  intellectuals, he believed, had sold their souls for ‘temporal domination’, for riches,

  for honours, for privileged positions, for political power, for earthly glory.

  Péguy’s text contained another theme of great resonance. Péguy repeatedly stated

  that he and his friends had been inspired by ‘warlike virtues’. And this he explained

  in terms of ‘a need for heroism, which seized an entire generation, our generation,

  131 Ibid. 648.

  132 Ibid. 508–9.

  133 Ibid. 520.

  134 Ibid. 521.

  135 See esp. ‘De la Situation faite au parti intellectuel dans le monde moderne’, in Œuvres en prose

  1898–1908 (1959), 1031–78 and ‘De la Situation faite au parti intellectuel dans le monde moderne

  devant les accidents de la gloire temporelle’, ibid. 1115–1214.

  462

  France, Intellectuals, and Engagement

  a need for war . . . a need for sacrifice to the point of martyrdom’.136 When the

  young Péguy had arrived from Orléans to pursue his studies at the École Normale

  Supérieure he had quickly converted to socialism and in his earliest writings had

  provided a description of the ‘cité socialiste’ as the ‘cité harmonieuse’. Then his

  hero had been Jean Jaurès. In the cheerless aftermath of the Dreyfus Affair Péguy

  held fast to the purity of his earliest convictions but he there began the journey that

  was later to see his pilgrimage to the cathedral of Chartres and his own death in the

  first battle of the Marne in September 1914. In many respects the contours of this

  journey can best be discerned by comparing his two treatments of the figure of

  Jeanne d’
Arc. The first, a dramatic trilogy published in 1897, ended with a plea for

  the ‘establishment of the Universal Socialist Republic’; the second, a long prose

  poem entitled Le Mystère de la Charité de Jeanne d’Arc published in 1910, focused

  upon the possibility of eternal life and salvation.

  For our purposes, however, we might also briefly consider Péguy’s essay of 1905,

  Notre Patrie.137 In its composition, it was typical of so many of Péguy’s lyrical

  outpourings. It opened with a description of the sorry plight of French politics

  under the premiership of Émile Combes but then used the state visit of the king of

  Spain as a pretext for a series of reflections about the people of the Paris and the

  city’s ‘imperishable monuments’. In effect, what Péguy sought to portray was the

  patrie as a physical and enduring reality, as something at once both eternal and

  immortal.138 But Péguy also saw that what was imperishable ‘will inevitably perish’.

  Here, the political context was not unimportant. In March of that year, Kaiser

  Wilhelm II had made a provocative and unexpected landing at Tangiers. The

  intention was to humiliate France by demonstrating the hollowness of her preten-

  sions in North Africa. To many––including Péguy––war with Germany again

  seemed inevitable. Convinced that invasion was imminent, he now wrote that ‘a

  new period had begun in the history of my own life, in the history of this country,

  and assuredly in the history of the world’.139 He was not to be mistaken. ‘Happy’,

  he was later to write in a premonition of his own death, ‘are those who die for an

  earthly land, when a just war calls.’

  Péguy’s erstwhile friend and colleague, Georges Sorel, also believed that ‘a great

  foreign war’ might renew France’s ‘lost energies’. His preferred solution to France’s

  ills,140 however, was a renewed bout of proletarian class struggle directed against a

  timorous and humanitarian bourgeoisie. In much the same way as he became

  disillusioned with the ‘Dreyfusard Revolution’, he quickly became disenchanted

  with the workers, and thus from 1909 to 1914 found himself participating in a

  series of publishing initiatives that brought together thinkers from the extremes of

  both the left and the right.141 One such initiative was the short-lived plan to

 

‹ Prev