Book Read Free

Revolution and the Republic

Page 100

by Jeremy Jennings


  executioners of Bolshevism’.202

  Ten years later it was the Italian invasion of Ethiopia and the threat of sanctions

  imposed by the League of Nations against the aggressors that provided the oppor-

  tunity for a virtual rerun of the same arguments, although with some new partici-

  pants. The right produced a ‘Manifeste des intellectuels pour la défense de

  l’Occident’ signed not only by sixteen members of the Académie Française but

  also by such luminaries as Robert Brasillach, Pierre Drieu la Rochelle, Pierre

  Gaxotte, Thierry Maulnier, and Charles Maurras. Condemning what it described

  as ‘a false legal universalism which sets the superior and the inferior, the civilized

  person and the barbarian, on the same equal footing’, it justified the right of all

  European nations to possess colonies in the name of the advancement and protec-

  tion of Western civilization.203 The response came first in the form of an appeal

  headed by the writer Jules Romains and then a ‘Manifeste pour la justice et la paix’,

  penned by philosopher Jacques Maritain and signed by, among others, Emmanuel

  Mounier. Both texts supported the League of Nations, but the latter in particular

  denied that the ‘mission of the people of the West’ could be accomplished by force

  of arms. Casting themselves as ‘the true representatives of French intelligence’, the

  signatories called for all governments to respect international law and to work for

  peace.204 The following three years––1936–8––saw similar petitions in response to

  the Spanish civil war, those for and against Franco, those for or against the Spanish

  Republic, those for or against intervention, claiming to defend civilization against

  either communism or military dictatorship. Interestingly, and as was the case with

  the war in Ethiopia, among those supporting the cause of the Spanish people were

  young Catholic writers such as François Mauriac and Georges Bernanos.

  The inter-war years, therefore, saw no evidence of de-mobilization on the part of

  France’s intellectuals. Indeed, if anything, their involvement in public affairs only

  intensified as France limped from one economic or diplomatic crisis to another and

  as disenchantment with the political system grew among the electorate. Curiously,

  if for the most part the participants in these debates now all seemed happy to

  describe themselves as intellectuals, discussion of the proper role of the intellectual

  in no way diminished. This was most clearly visible in Julien Benda’s text of 1927,

  La Trahison des clercs, and in Paul Nizan’s later polemical riposte, Les Chiens de

  garde.205

  When the quarrel between Daniel Halèvy and Charles Péguy broke out, one

  of the people who had acted as an intermediary was Julien Benda. He had been

  202 Sirinelli, Intellectuels et passions françaises, 64–5.

  203 Ibid. 92–4.

  204 Ibid. 96–8.

  205 See Ray Nichols, Treason, Tradition and the Intellectual: Julien Benda and Political Discourse

  (Lawrence, Kan., 1978) and David L. Schalk, The Spectrum of Political Engagement (Princeton, 1979).

  France, Intellectuals, and Engagement

  473

  drawn into Péguy’s circle at an early age and like them had thrown his weight

  behind the Dreyfusard cause. The mental outlook that had informed this political

  commitment was later spelt out by Benda in a volume of memoirs entitled La

  Jeunesse d’un clerc. It was this same outlook that informed the argument of his more

  famous essay on the betrayal of the intellectuals.

  The first two sections of La Jeunesse d’un clerc focused upon Benda’s family

  upbringing and his school years. What emerged was a picture of someone whose

  Jewishness was felt through an attachment to certain abstract values rather than as a

  religion and where those values––civil equality, the elimination of privilege, indi-

  vidual liberty, and the religious neutrality of the State––were also the values of the

  Republic. His republican education further reinforced his sense of loyalty to these

  values, producing a ‘mandarin’ with no sense of ‘the particularity of his nation, his

  ancestors, or his race’.206 The result was a vision of the intellectual consciously

  modelled upon the medieval cleric withdrawn from the daily realities of the world

  and whose function it was to meditate and to reflect, ‘not to act but to think’.207 As

  Benda later explained, the task of the ‘true intellectual’ was ‘to think correctly and

  to find the truth, without concern with what will happen to the planet as a

  result’.208

  ‘Not everyone’, Benda wrote, ‘has the opportunity at the threshold of their lives

  to make an abrupt choice between two very different moralities and to know what

  they are.’209 This was what the Dreyfus Affair had enabled him to do. ‘In a flash’,

  Benda wrote, he had understood ‘the hierarchy of values’ that formed ‘his very

  essence’ and ‘the visceral hatred’ he felt for opposing views. From this point

  onwards he had held firm to the belief that truth and justice were ‘abstract values’

  separate from the interests of either time or place. He had therefore opposed the

  position taken by Barrès not simply because it was ‘profoundly anti-French’ but

  also on the grounds that it constituted ‘the systematic destruction’ of everything

  since Socrates that had sought to raise human beings above their ‘individual or

  group egoisms’.210 Similarly Benda had no time for those Dreyfusards who were

  motivated by human compassion for the innocent Dreyfus languishing on Devil’s

  Island. His protest, Benda wrote, had been an act of ‘pure intellectuality’, an

  affirmation of truth in the face of error.

  This was the position that underpinned the argument advanced in La Trahison

  des clercs. Restated in more polemical terms he here defined the clercs as ‘all those

  whose activity in essence is not the pursuit of practical ends and who, seeking their

  joy in the pursuit of an art or a science or in metaphysical speculation, in short, in

  the possession of non-temporal advantages, say in a certain manner: “My kingdom

  is not of this world”’.211 This was not intended as a purely prescriptive account of

  how the intellectual ought to act, as this, Benda believed, was precisely how the

  clercs had operated in the past. ‘Thanks to them’, Benda wrote, ‘it might be said that

  if, for over thousand years, humanity did evil it had honoured the good.’212

  206 La Jeunesse d’un clerc (1936), 50.

  207 Ibid. 121.

  208 Précision (1930–1937) (1937), 19.

  209 La Jeunesse d’un clerc, 203–4.

  210 Ibid. 198.

  211 La Trahison des clercs (1977), 194.

  212 Ibid. 195.

  474

  France, Intellectuals, and Engagement

  Moreover, it was precisely in this manner, according to Benda, that men such as

  Zola and Duclaux had acted during the Dreyfus Affair. ‘They had been’, Benda

  argued, ‘the officiants of abstract justice and had not been sullied by any passion for

  a worldly objective.’213

  Benda’s complaint, however, was that ‘at the end of the nineteenth century’ the

  clercs had ceased to exist as ‘a class of men’ separate and distinct from the multitu
de

  and that they had subordinated their mission to the service of political passions. In

  so doing, they had abased the values of knowledge before the values of action and

  the cult of success. Doing nothing to resist the passions of race, class, and

  nationality, Benda affirmed, the ‘modern clercs . . . had set about proclaiming that

  the intellectual function is respectable only to the extent that it is connected to the

  pursuit of concrete advantage and that the intelligence which is disinterested in

  these ends is to be scorned’.214 The list of culprits was extensive and was not

  exclusively French––both Rudyard Kipling and Friedrich Nietzsche were cited by

  Benda, for example––but among the French writers accused of proclaiming the

  superiority of instinct, the unconscious, and the will over intelligence were Brune-

  tière, Barrès, Maurras, Georges Sorel, and Péguy.

  How could this ‘great betrayal’ be explained? Benda proffered three principal

  explanations. The first, and most important, was that the present age was the age of

  politics, the ‘century of the intellectual organization of political hatreds’.215

  ‘Today’, Benda wrote, ‘political passions possess a degree of universality, of coher-

  ence, of homogeneity, of precision, of continuity, of preponderance over other

  passions, not previously known.’216 The clercs had come to share these passions and

  hatreds and to embrace what Benda termed ‘the realism of the masses’. The second

  cause identified by Benda was ‘the decline in the study of classical literature’ and

  with that a lesser appreciation of what was ‘human in its universal aspect’.217 In

  effect, the charge was one of a loss of intellectual discipline. The third explanation

  drew upon an altogether different conjecture, and one that has since informed

  many critiques of the intellectual’s supposed autonomy: the clercs had descended to

  the market place ‘in the interests of their careers’.218 Rather than the pursuit of

  knowledge as an end in itself, their goals were now fame, honours, and social status.

  ‘The Bohemian man of letters’, Benda wrote, is ‘a figure who has practically

  disappeared’.219 In similar vein, elsewhere Benda wrote that ‘one of the great

  treasons of the modern clerc is marriage’.220

  La Trahison des clercs was a deeply flawed book. It was also a self-serving book,

  designed not only to justify the position taken by Benda during the Dreyfus Affair

  but also his support of the French war effort in 1914. Roman Rolland, for example,

  was criticized for his ‘mystic pacifism’. It also proved to be a controversial book and

  one to which Benda himself had to return on numerous subsequent occasions as he

  sought to steer a course through the turbulent political environment of the 1930s

  and 1940s. To the end, he believed that he had remained true to his original

  213 La Trahison des clercs (1977), 200.

  214 Ibid. 293.

  215 Ibid. 180–1

  216 Ibid. 182.

  217 Ibid. 312.

  218 Ibid. 303.

  219 Ibid. 306.

  220 ‘Le Clerc et la famille’, Précision, 9.

  France, Intellectuals, and Engagement

  475

  principles, writing in the preface to the 1946 edition of La Trahison des clercs that

  ‘when injustice becomes master of the world and the entire universe kneels before

  it, the clerc must remain standing and confront it with the human conscience’.221 It

  was, on the other hand, precisely this argument that provoked the blistering attack

  directed against Benda by Paul Nizan in Les Chiens de garde.

  Born in 1905 into a petit-bourgeois provincial family,222 Paul Nizan entered

  the École Normale Supérieure in Paris in 1924 to study for the agrégation in

  philosophy. One of his fellow students (and soon to be a close friend) was Jean-

  Paul Sartre.223 Unlike his more famous colleague, Nizan was quickly attracted

  to Marxism and in 1927 he joined the French Communist Party, subsequently

  writing for La Revue Marxiste and a series of other left-wing publications.224 In

  1931 he published Aden Arabie and then, a year later, Les Chiens de garde. The

  former drew upon his experiences in the British colony of Aden where, in 1926,

  he had secured a post working for Antonin Besse.225 Nizan’s first-hand experience

  of colonial exploitation did much to confirm his hostility towards capitalism but

  the early chapters of Aden Arabie also provided a vivid, and unreservedly hostile,

  portrayal of his own education. It was an account that differed markedly from

  that provided by Benda in La Jeunesse d’un clerc. Of his fellow students at the École

  Normale Supérieure, he wrote that they were ‘exhausted by their years at the lycée,

  were corrupted by the humanities and by the bourgeois morals and cooking of their

  families’.226 They were nothing else, in Nizan’s opinion, than elitist hypocrites. As

  for his professors, they were men who believed that ‘problems will no longer exist

  when the terms of debate are conveniently defined’ and that the Good amounted to

  keeping the people in a position of subservience.227 They acted, Nizan wrote, as

  ‘watchdogs of vocabulary’.

  The starting point of Les Chiens de garde was that all philosophies had a bearing

  upon the world. ‘Every philosopher,’ Nizan argued, ‘though he may consider that

  he does not, participates in the impure reality of his age.’228 Moreover, all philo-

  sophies were either beneficial or detrimental to the interests of humankind. There

  was, therefore, ‘a philosophy for the oppressors and a philosophy for the op-

  pressed’.229 Thus, to speak of the abstract and eternal notions of Truth and

  Justice––which, in any case, did not exist––was to divert attention from the things

  that really mattered to the inhabitants of the earth––‘war, colonialism, the rational-

  ization of industry, love, the varieties of death, unemployment’––and was to put up

  a smokescreen before the economic, social, and political realities constituting the

  everyday oppression of ordinary people. If, then, as Nizan believed, the proper

  221 La Trahison, 135–6.

  222 On Nizan see W. D. Redfern, Paul Nizan: Committed Literature in a Conspirational World

  (Princeton, NJ, 1972) and Annie Cohen-Solal, Paul Nizan, communiste impossible (1980).

  223 When Nizan married in 1927 his two witnesses at the ceremony were Sartre and Raymond

  Aron.

  224 See Jean-Jacques Brochier (ed.), Paul Nizan: Intellectuel Communiste 1926–1940 (2001).

  225 Besse subsequently provided the money to establish St Antony’s College, Oxford.

  226 Aden Arabie (1931), 16.

  227 Ibid. 14, 18.

  228 Les Chiens de garde (1998), 34.

  229 Ibid. 57.

  476

  France, Intellectuals, and Engagement

  function of philosophy was to serve the real interests of real people, to adopt a

  position of ‘impartiality or indifference’ was to take sides. From this he concluded

  that ‘the desire to be a clerc and only a clerc is less a choice made by an eternal man

  than the decision of a partisan. To abstain is to make a choice and to express a

  preference.’230

  This was the charge levelled against those Nizan described as ‘the fraternal

 
enemies’ who made up the world of French philosophy: Benda certainly, but also

  Bergson and Émile Boutroux, and, above all, Léon Brunschvicg from the Sor-

  bonne. ‘The audacity of their philosophy’, Nizan affirmed, ‘consists in identifying

  human society, all possible human societies, with bourgeois society, and human

  reason, all possible forms of human reason, with bourgeois reason.’231 Nor did

  Nizan leave his readers in any doubt as to the consequences of such hollow

  bourgeois rhetoric. Arguing that to have defended Dreyfus was to have supported

  the bourgeoisie, he claimed that ‘when the victim of a violation of justice is a

  proletarian there is no reaction at all from philosophy’.232 More than this, it had

  been these very same men who had provided the philosophical justification for

  France’s war against Germany. ‘These clercs’, Nizan fumed, ‘simply emulated the

  crowd and followed the orders of the generals and the politicians. These men, most

  of whom were not subject to mobilization, meekly went along with the forces of

  ignorance and exhorted those who had been mobilized to give up their lives. Every

  one of their students who fell in battle was a martyr to their philosophy.’233

  Nizan’s explanation of this duplicity demolished any claim to autonomy on the

  part of the bourgeois intellectual. ‘It is especially worthy of note’, Nizan observed,

  ‘that, generally speaking, our thinkers are salaried employees of the State, that the

  leading opinions in this country are produced in exchange for public monies and

  are backed by government sanctions.’234 The Republic, in other words, had

  successfully replaced the spiritual guardians of the old monarchical and ecclesiasti-

  cal order with a ‘secular clergy’. This new clergy, Nizan continued, now discharged

  exactly the same functions as its predecessor, generating ‘all the forms of moral

  suasion, all the spiritual propaganda which the State might require’.235 Intellec-

  tuals––and specifically France’s humanist philosophers––were nothing else but the

  purveyors of ‘the philosophy of the State’.236

  Nizan’s claim therefore was that it was in their attachment to the world of the

  bourgeoisie that lay the real ‘trahison des clercs’.237 For that reason an alternative

  model to the ‘contemplative clerc’ of ‘bourgeois thought’ was required and this,

 

‹ Prev