Book Read Free

The Meaning of Human Existence

Page 13

by Edward O. Wilson


  This lack of utility is not due to any technical oversight. Rather, it arises from the attempt to extend Hamilton’s rule to every instance of natural selection. This impulse is understandable, given the intuitive appeal of Hamilton’s original formulation. However, the power of a theoretical framework is derived from its assumptions, thus a theory with no assumptions cannot predict or explain anything. As Wittgenstein argued in his Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus, any statement that is true in all situations contains no specific information about any particular situation.

  There Is No Universal Design Principle

  The concept of inclusive fitness arises when one attempts to explain the evolution of social behavior at the level of the individual. For example, inclusive fitness theory seeks to explain the existence of sterile ant workers in terms of the behaviors of the workers themselves. The proposed explanation is that workers maximize their inclusive fitness by helping the queen rather than producing their own offspring.

  The claim that evolution maximizes inclusive fitness has been interpreted as a universal design principle for evolution. This claim is based on an argument by Hamilton that evolution maximizes the mean inclusive fitness of a population, and a separate argument by Alan Grafen that evolved organisms act as if to maximize their inclusive fitness. Both of these arguments depend on restrictive assumptions, including additivity of fitness effects. Because experiments have shown that fitness effects in real biological populations are nonadditive, these results cannot be expected to hold in general. Moreover, both theory and experiment have shown that frequency-dependent selection can lead to complex dynamic phenomena such as multiple and mixed equilibria, limit cycles, and chaotic attractors, ruling out the possibility of general maximands. Thus, evolution does not, in general, lead to the maximization of inclusive fitness or any other quantity.

  Commonsense Approaches to Evolutionary Theory

  Fortunately, no universal maximands or design principles are needed to understand the evolution of social behavior. Rather, we may rely on a straightforward genetic approach: Consider mutations that modify behavior. Under which conditions are these mutations favored (or disfavored) by natural selection? The target of selection is not the individual, but the allele or the genomic ensemble that affects behavior.

  To investigate these questions theoretically, one needs modeling assumptions. These assumptions can be highly specific, applying only to particular biological situations, or broad, applying to a wide range of scenarios. Modeling frameworks that rely on general (yet precise) assumptions have recently emerged as a powerful tool for studying the evolution of populations structured spatially, by groups, and physiologically; the evolution of continuous traits; and inclusive fitness theory itself (in cases where fitness effects are additive and other requirements are satisfied). Although these frameworks can be used to obtain general results, none of them is universal or assumption-free. Instead, they draw upon their assumptions to make well-defined, testable predictions about the systems to which they apply.

  Discussion

  Inclusive fitness theory attempts to find a universal design principle for evolution that applies at the level of the individual. The result is an unobservable quantity that does not exist in general (if additivity is required) or has no predictive or explanatory value (if the regression method is used). If instead we take a genetic perspective and ask whether natural selection will favor or oppose alleles that modify social behavior, there is no need for inclusive fitness.

  The dominance of inclusive fitness theory has held up progress in this area for many decades. It has consistently suppressed reasonable criticism and alternative approaches. In particular, the attempt to eschew the requirement of additivity using regression methods has led to logical obfuscation and false claims of universality. Reasonable inclusive fitness calculations that assume additivity represent an alternative method to account for fitness effects in some limited situations, but this method is never necessary and often needlessly complicated. There is no problem in evolutionary biology that requires an analysis based on inclusive fitness.

  Having realized the limitations of inclusive fitness, sociobiology now has the possibility to move forward. We encourage the development of realistic models grounded in a firm understanding of natural history. With the aid of population genetics, evolutionary game theory, and new analytic procedures to be developed, a strong and resilient sociobiological theory can emerge.

  Acknowledgments

  I am grateful to John Taylor (Ike) Williams for his unwavering support and advice, to Robert Weil for his editorial guidance on this as on my earlier books published by W. W. Norton, and to Kathleen M. Horton for her invaluable assistance in research, editorial work, and manuscript preparation.

  Chapter 2, “Solving the Riddle of the Human Species,” is a modification of the author’s “The Riddle of the Human Species,” in The New York Times Opinionator, February 24, 2013. Chapter 3, “Evolution and Our Inner Conflict” was modified from an article of that name by the author, in The New York Times Opinionator, June 24, 2012. Chapter 11, “The Collapse of Biodiversity,” is a modified version of “Beware the Age of Loneliness,” in The World in 2014, The Economist, November 2013, p. 143.

  Index

  Page numbers listed correspond to the print edition of this book. You can use your device’s search function to locate particular terms in the text.

  Absolute Paradox (Kierkegaard), 157–58

  academia, Harvard, 40–41

  Age of Loneliness (Eremocene), 123

  alien life, 45, 53–55, 102–4, 106

  Allen, Benjamin, 74, 189–202

  allomones, 81–82

  anole lizards, 138

  Antarctica, life, 104

  Anthropocene, 123

  anthropocentricity, 42–43

  ants, 65, 83, 86–88, 95–97, 166

  arachnophobia, 139–40

  archaeans, 47, 104, 108, 111

  artificial life, 58

  australopiths, 175

  Bacon, Francis, 38, 133, 136

  bacteria, communication, 89 see also microbes

  BAM (Brain Activity Map), 163–64

  biodiversity, 46–50, 123–32

  biosphere, 46–50

  bird song, 81

  BNR (biology, nanotechnology, robotics), 58

  brain, human,see mind

  Bruller, Jean, 135

  campsites, 21–22

  Carlson, Anton J., 153

  causation, proximate versus ultimate, 15

  chimpanzees, 175

  Churchland, Patricia, 161

  confliction, moral, 27–34

  confabulation, 167–68

  conquest of galaxy, 119–22

  conscience, origin, 27–34, 179–80

  consciousness, 159–70

  consilience (unity of knowledge), 35–75

  continuum, concept, examples, 44–52, 167, 186

  cooperation, origin, 21–22, 29–31

  Copernicus, 46

  Creationism, 183–85

  creation stories, 12, 18, 151–58, 181–85

  creative arts, 17, 22, 35–75, 79, 186

  culture, origin, 37–75, 80, 100, 105, 141–46

  Darwin, Charles, 29, 162–63, 178, 183

  Dawkins, Richard, 70, 73

  Deinococcus, 104–5

  Dennett, Daniel, 161

  driver ants, 92–94

  driving forces of evolution, 23–24, 61–75, 189–202

  dysfunction, innate human property, 176–80

  ecosystems, 105, 120, 124–26, 144

  Edelman, Gerald, 159

  emergent evolution, 165

  emotion, 167 see also mind; phobias

  Enceladus, 105–6

  Enlightenment, 37–40, 51–52

  Eremozoic Era, 123

  E.T., 104–22

  eugenics, 58–59

  Europa (moon of Jupiter), 106

  eusociality, 18–20, 61–75

  in humans, 20–21, 61–7
5, 189–202

  evil, 27, 179

  evolution, driving forces, 23–24, 61–75, 189–202

  existential conservatism, 60

  exoplanets, 44–46, 102–9

  extinction, 127–32

  extraterrestrial life, 102–22

  extremist, religion, 154–55

  extremophiles, 104–6, 109

  faith, religious, 151–58

  fishes, electric, 49–50

  forces, evolution, 23–24, 61–75, 189–202

  Founding Fathers, U.S., 155–56

  free will, 159–70

  Galileo, 46

  gene-culture coevolution, 56

  God, 31, 33–34, 148–50

  gods, Greek, 43

  gossip, 142

  habitat, selection, 143–46

  Haldane, J. B. S., 66–69

  Hamilton, William D., 67–70, 189–202

  Hamilton inequality, 67–70, 189–202

  Harvard University, faculty, 40–41

  hearing, 48

  history of life, 56 see also human prehistory

  Hofstadter, Douglas, 166

  honeybees, 100

  human evolution, 17–26, 43, 58–59, 111

  Human Genome Project, 163

  humanities, definition, 17, 35–75, 174

  humanity, as dysfunctional species, 176–79

  human nature, 136–37, 143–46

  human prehistory, 17–26, 74–75, 80, 89–90, 111, 175–76

  Human Relation Area Files, 143

  IF theory (inclusive fitness theory),see forces, evolution

  inclusive fitness,see forces, evolution

  instinct, 29–31, 100–101, 135–46

  human, 139–46

  Kepler space telescope, 106

  keystone species, 126

  Kierkegaard, Søren, 157

  kin selection,see forces, evolution

  kitten, instinctive play, 43–44

  leafcutters, ants, 97–99

  Lewis, C. S., 157

  Madison, James, 156

  mathematics, 142

  meaning of “meaning,” 12–16

  memory, origin, role, 22–23

  microbes, 102–9

  microorganisms, 102–9

  mind, 24, 159–70

  see also creative arts; culture, origin; Enlightenment; human nature; instinct; pheromones; phobias; senses, human; social intelligence

  mole rats, 32, 111

  monkeys, 42–43, 114, 175

  moral reasoning, 40

  Mormonism, 156

  moths, pheromones, 48, 84

  music, antiquity, 147–48

  natural selection, 13–14, 18–19, 28–29

  nematodes (roundworms), 105, 125

  neuroscience of religion, 148

  Nietzsche, Friedrich, 12

  Nowak, Martin A., 72–75, 189–202

  pangenesis (microbial space travel), 108–9

  Paul (prophet), 11

  pheromones, 79–91

  phobias, 139–42

  picozoans, 47, 48, 104, 111

  Pius XII, Pope, 153

  plants, communication, 88–89

  Pledge of Allegiance, U.S., 156

  poetry, origin, nature, 41–43

  pollinators, social, 100

  prehistory, human, 32–34

  proximate causation, 15

  qualia, 161

  racism, 31

  religion, 31, 40, 147–58

  robots, 33, 58–59, 106, 118, 121

  Romney, Mitt, 156

  Sagan, Carl, 27

  Satan, 33, 183

  science, qualities, relation to humanities, 17–18, 44–75

  selection forces, evolution, 23–24, 61–75, 189–202

  selection, group, 23–24, 29–30

  selection, multilevel, 23–24

  selection, natural, 14, 18–19, 28–29

  selection, volitional, 14

  Seneca the Younger, 153

  senses, human, 48–50

  sin, 30–34, 175–76

  SLIMES (deep biosphere), 105

  smell, 49, 79–91

  snakes:

  olfaction, 85

  phobia, 141

  social intelligence, 22, 23, 30, 32, 43, 75, 116

  social networks, 30

  soul,see mind; religion

  sound, communication, 81

  spiders, 93, 105, 116, 125, 139–41

  spirituality, 148–55

  stickleback (fish), 137–38

  storytelling, 167–68

  success, of ants and termites, 99

  superorganisms, 92, 165–66

  Tarnita, Corina, 72–74

  taste, 49–75, 79–91

  taxonomy, 125–26

  Teresa of Ávila, Saint, 147

  termite societies, 166

  theology, 148–49

  tolerable parasite load, human, 180

  tribalism, 150–54

  turtles, instinct, 138–39

  ultimate causation, 15

  unification, science and humanities, 12, 35–75

  Vercors (Jean Bruller), 135

  virtue, 30–34

  viruses, 47, 104, 108, 111

  vision, 48–49

  volitional selection, 14, 59 see also other forms under selection

  Vostok, Lake, 106

  war, 154–55

  warning coloration, 81–82

  Washington, George, 156

  About the Author

  EDWARD OSBORNE WILSON is generally recognized as one of the several leading biologists in the world. He is acknowledged as the creator of two scientific disciplines (island biogeography and sociobiology), three unifying concepts for science and the humanities jointly (biophilia, biodiversity studies, and consilience), and one major technological advance in the study of global biodiversity (the Encyclopedia of Life). Among more than one hundred awards he has received worldwide are the U.S. National Medal of Science, the Crafoord Prize (equivalent of the Nobel, for ecology) of the Royal Swedish Academy of Sciences, the International Prize of Biology of Japan; and in letters, two Pulitzer Prizes in nonfiction, the Nonino and Serono Prizes of Italy, and the COSMOS prize of Japan. He is currently Honorary Curator in Entomology and University Research Professor Emeritus, Harvard University.

  ALSO BY EDWARD O. WILSON

  A Window on Eternity: Gorongosa National Park, Mozambique (2014)

  Letters to a Young Scientist (2013)

  Why We Are Here: Mobile and the Spirit of a Southern City,

  with Alex Harris (2012)

  The Social Conquest of Earth (2012)

  Kingdom of Ants: José Celestino Mutis and the Dawn of Natural History in the New World, with José M. Gómez Durán (2011)

  The Leafcutter Ants: Civilization by Instinct, with Bert Hölldobler (2011)

  Anthill: A Novel (2010)

  The Superorganism: The Beauty, Elegance and Strangeness of Insect Societies,

  with Bert Hölldobler (2009)

  The Creation: An Appeal to Save Life on Earth (2006)

  Nature Revealed: Selected Writings, 1949–2006 (2006)

  From So Simple a Beginning: The Four Great Books of Darwin,

  edited with introductions (2005)

  Pheidole in the New World: A Dominant, Hyperdiverse Ant Genus (2003)

 

‹ Prev