Book Read Free

The Politics Book

Page 14

by DK Publishing


  Rousseau was not against property, so long as it was distributed fairly. He considered a small, agrarian republic in which all citizens were smallholders to be an ideal form of state.

  A new contract

  Rousseau did not equate this idea of popular sovereignty with democracy as such, fearing that a directly democratic government, requiring all citizens to participate, was uniquely prone to corruption and civil war. Instead, he envisaged sovereignty being invested in popular assemblies capable of delegating the tasks of government – via a new social contract, or a constitution – to an executive. The sovereign people would embody the “general will”, an expression of popular assent. Day-to-day government, however, would depend on specific decisions, requiring a “particular will”.

  It was in this very distinction, Rousseau thought, that conflict between the “general will” and the “particular will” opened up, paving the way for the corruption of the sovereign people. It was this corruption that so marked the world of Rousseau’s time, in his view. Instead of acting as a collective, sovereign body, the people were consumed by the pursuit of private interests. In place of the freedom of popular sovereignty, society had pushed people into separate, private spheres of endeavour, whether in the arts, science, or literature, or in the division of labour. This numbed people into habitual deference, and instilled a spirit of passivity.

  To ensure the government was an authentic expression of the popular, general will, Rousseau believed that participation in its assemblies and procedures should be compulsory, removing – as far as possible – the temptations of the private will. But this belief in the necessity of combating private desires is exactly where Rousseau’s later, liberal critics have found the deepest fault.

  Private versus general will

  The “general will”, however desirable in theory, could easily be vested in deeply oppressive arrangements. Not least was the difficulty in actually ascertaining the “general will”. The road for an individual or a group claiming to express the general will, when merely exercising their own particular wills, was clearly wide open. Rousseau, in desiring to make the people sovereign, could be presented as the forefather of totalitarianism. What repressive regime since his time has not attempted to claim the support of “the people”?

  Indeed, Rousseau’s provisions against factions and divisions among the people – which he, like Machiavelli, saw as undermining the state – could certainly turn into a tyranny of the majority, in which unpopular minorities suffer at the hands of those exercising the “general will”. Rousseau’s recommendation for dealing with this dilemma was to recognize the inevitability of factions, and to multiply them indefinitely – making so many particular wills that no one of them would stand a chance of representing the general will, nor would any one faction be dominant enough to oppose the general will.

  States formed under illegitimate social contracts based on the fraud of the powerful were not capable of expressing this will, precisely because their subjects were bound to them only by deference to authority, not by mutual assent. However, if the apparent contracts between rulers and ruled were illegitimate, based on a denial of people’s sovereignty rather than its expression, it would follow that the people had every right to depose their rulers. That, at least, is how the more radical of Rousseau’s later followers came to interpret him. Rousseau himself was at best ambiguous on the issue of outright revolt, frequently denouncing violence and civil unrest and urging respect for existing laws.

  The French Revolution began when an angry mob stormed the Bastille in Paris on 14 July 1789. The medieval fortress and prison was a symbol of royal power.

  A revolutionary icon

  Rousseau’s belief in the sovereignty of the people, and the perfectibility of both people and society, has had an immense impact. In the French Revolution, the Jacobins adopted him as a figurehead for their own belief in the necessity of a ruthlessly complete, egalitarian transformation of French society. In 1794, he was reinterred in the Panthéon, Paris, as a national hero. Over the next two centuries, Rousseau’s work also acted as a touchstone for all those who wished to see society radically overhauled for the common good, from Karl Marx onwards.

  "We are approaching a state of crisis and the age of revolutions."

  Jean-Jacques Rousseau

  Similarly, the arguments against Rousseau, during his life and after, have helped to shape both conservative and liberal thought. In 1791, Edmund Burke, one of the founders of modern conservatism, held Rousseau to be almost personally responsible for the French Revolution and what he saw as its excesses. Writing almost 200 years later, the radical-liberal philosopher Hannah Arendt believed the errors in Rousseau’s thinking helped to drive the Revolution away from its liberal roots.

  JEAN-JACQUES ROUSSEAU

  Jean-Jacques Rousseau was born in Geneva, Switzerland. The son of a freeman entitled to vote in city elections, he never wavered in his appreciation of Geneva’s liberal institutions. Inheriting a large library and a voracious appetite for reading, Rousseau received no formal education. At the age of 15, an introduction to the noblewoman Françoise-Louise de Warens led to his conversion to Catholicism, exile from Geneva, and disownment by his father.

  Rousseau began studying in earnest in his 20s and was appointed secretary to the ambassador to Venice in 1743. He left soon after for Paris, where he built a reputation as a controversial essayist. When his books were banned in France and Geneva, he fled briefly to London, but soon returned to France where he spent the rest of his life.

  Key works

  1754 Discourse on the Origin and Basis of Inequality Among Men

  1762 Emile

  1762 The Social Contract

  1770 Confessions

  See also: Ibn Khaldun • Niccolò Machiavelli • Hugo Grotius • Thomas Hobbes • Edmund Burke • Hannah Arendt

  IN CONTEXT

  IDEOLOGY

  Freedom

  FOCUS

  Personal responsibility

  BEFORE

  380 BCE Plato argues in the Republic that the state’s main aim is to ensure the happiness of all people.

  1689 In his Second Treatise on Government, John Locke states that by a “social contract” people delegate their right of self-protection to government.

  AFTER

  1851 Pierre-Joseph Proudhon argues that the social contract should be between individuals, not between individuals and government.

  1971 In his book A Theory of Justice, John Rawls combines Kant’s idea of autonomy with Social Choice theory.

  In 1793, the great German philosopher Immanuel Kant wrote an essay entitled “On the Common Saying: ‘That may be right in theory, but it does not work in practice’”, which is often now referred to simply as Theory and Practice. The essay was written in a year of momentous political change: George Washington became the first president of the US, the German city of Mainz declared itself an independent republic, and the French Revolution reached its height with the execution of King Louis XVI and Marie Antoinette. Kant’s essay examined not only political theory and practice, but also the legitimacy of government itself. This was a topic that had become literally a matter of life or death.

  In stating that “no generally valid principle of legislation can be based on happiness”, Kant argues with a position taken by the Greek philosopher Plato some 2,000 years earlier. Kant’s essay states that happiness does not work as a basis for law. No one can – nor should – try to define what happiness is for someone else, so a rule based on happiness cannot be applied consistently. “For… the highly conflicting and variable illusions as to what happiness is,” Kant wrote, “… make all fixed principles impossible, so that happiness alone can never be a suitable principle of legislation.” What is crucial instead, he believed, is that the state ensures people’s freedom within the law “so that each remains free to seek his happiness in whatever way he thinks best, so long as he does not violate the lawful freedom and rights of his fellow subjects at large.
” Kant considers what would happen in a society where people live “in a state of nature”, free to pursue their own desires. He sees the main problem as a conflict of interests. What do you do, for instance, if your neighbour moves into your house and throws you out, and there are no laws to stop him or give you any redress? Kant claims that a state of nature is a recipe for anarchy, in which disputes cannot be settled peacefully. For this reason, people willingly “abandon the state of nature… in order to submit to external public and lawful coercion.” Kant’s position follows on from the English philosopher John Locke’s earlier idea of the social contract, which says that people make a contract with the state in which they each freely consent to give up some of their freedom in exchange for the state’s protection.

  King Louis XVI of France was executed in 1793. For Kant, the French Revolution was a warning to all governments that they must rule for the good of all the people.

  The consent of all

  Kant asserts that governments must remember that they govern only by the people’s consent – not the consent of a few people, nor even a majority, but of the entire population. What counts is that no one among the population might potentially object to a proposed law. “For if the law is such that a whole people could not possibly agree to it, it is unjust; but if it is at least possible that a people could agree to it, it is our duty to consider the law just.”

  Kant’s idea acts as an important guide for the citizen as well as the government, because he is also saying that if a government passes a law that you consider wrong, it is still your moral duty to obey it. You might think it is wrong to pay taxes to your government to fund a war, but you should not withhold your taxes because you feel the war is unjust or unnecessary, because “it is at least possible that the war is inevitable and the tax indispensable”.

  "No one can compel me to be happy in accordance with his conception of the welfare of others."

  Immanuel Kant

  However, for Kant, although subjects have a duty to obey the law, they also have to take individual responsibility for their moral choices. He says that morals have a “categorical imperative”. By this, he means that an individual should only follow rules or maxims that they believe should apply to everyone. Each person, he says, must act as though they were law-makers through each of the moral choices they make.

  Kant’s categorical imperative states that you should act only according to rules or maxims that you would wish to be universally applicable. The state should not pass laws that do not meet this criterion.

  The will of the people

  At the heart of Kant’s philosophy – and applicable to both morality and politics – is the notion of autonomy. This is the idea that the human will is and must be wholly independent. Freedom is not being unbound by any law, but being bound by laws of one’s own making. The link between morals and state laws is direct: the legitimacy of both morality and laws is that they are based on the rational desires of the people; the social contract is “based on a coalition of the wills of all private individuals in a nation”. State laws must be literally “the will of the people”. So, if we agree to be governed, we must rationally agree to obey every law the government passes. By the same token, though, the laws of an external government, such as an occupying force or colonial power, have no legitimacy. Kant asks whether a government has a role in promoting the happiness of its people. He is clear that since only an individual can decide what makes him happy, any legislation designed to improve people’s lot must be based on their actual wishes, not what the government believes will be good for them. Nor should a government compel individuals to make other people happy. It cannot, for example, force you to go and see your grandmother regularly, even though it might be good for the country’s general happiness if grandmothers were properly appreciated.

  A state without happiness?

  Some commentators have argued that Kant does not see happiness as playing any part in government thinking. If this were the case, however, the state would do no more than protect its citizens physically. It would have no business providing education, building things such as hospitals, art galleries and museums, roads, and railways, or in looking after people’s welfare in any way. This position may be logically consistent, but it is not a recipe for a state that very many of us would want to live under.

  "All right consists solely in the restriction of the freedom of others."

  Immanuel Kant

  All the same, in the last 50 years, some thinkers have used this interpretation of Kant as a basis for the privatization of state industries, and for the dismantling of the welfare system on the grounds that it is an infringement of individual freedom to expect people to pay taxes for other people’s happiness. However, other commentators believe this is a misunderstanding of Kant’s position. They claim that Kant is not necessarily saying the promotion of happiness should not play a part in the thinking of the state – just that happiness cannot be the sole criterion. In addition, Kant points out that happiness can only be found after a solid constitution, outlining the role of the state, is already in place. In Theory and Practice, he says “the doctrine that ‘the public welfare is the supreme law of the state’ retains its value and authority undiminished; but the public welfare which demands first consideration lies precisely in that legal constitution which guarantees everyone his freedom within the law.”

  Rights and happiness

  Two years before Theory and Practice, in an essay entitled Perpetual Peace, Kant wrote that governments have two sets of duties: to protect the rights and liberties of the people as a matter of justice; and to promote the happiness of the people, as long as they can do this without diminishing the rights and freedom of the people. In recent years, commentators have wondered whether governments, perhaps still powerfully influenced by the narrower interpretation of Kant’s advice, have concentrated too much on economics and justice and left happiness out of the picture. Responding to these criticisms, in 2008 France’s then president Nicolas Sarkozy commissioned a report from a team led by US economist Joseph Stiglitz to measure his country’s “wellbeing”.

  Intervention in Afghanistan may be unpopular with the public in the US and Europe but, according to Kant, this discontent does not give individuals the right to withhold their taxes.

  IMMANUEL KANT

  The German philosopher Immanuel Kant was born in Königsberg, Prussia (now Kaliningrad in Russia), and lived there his whole life. The fourth of nine children of Lutheran parents, he was educated at a Lutheran school, where he gained a love of Latin but took a strong dislike to religious introspection. At the age of 16, he enrolled as a theology student, but soon became fascinated by philosophy, mathematics, and physics.

  Kant worked at the University of Königsberg as an unpaid lecturer and sub-librarian for 15 years before becoming a professor of logic and metaphysics at the age of 46. He gained international fame with the publication of his Critiques, and continued to teach for the rest of his life. He is considered by many to be the greatest thinker of the 18th century.

  Key works

  1781 Critique of Pure Reason (revised 1787)

  1788 Critique of Practical Reason

  1793 Theory and Practice

  See also: Plato • Thomas Hobbes • John Locke • Jean-Jacques Rousseau • Jeremy Bentham • John Rawls

  IN CONTEXT

  IDEOLOGY

  Conservativism

  FOCUS

  Political tradition

  BEFORE

  1688 English landowners force the abdication of James II in the Glorious Revolution.

  1748 Montesquieu asserts that liberty is maintained in England by a balance of power in different parts of society.

  AFTER

  1790–91 Paine’s Rights of Man and Wollstonecraft’s A Vindication of the Rights of Woman counter Burke’s work.

  1867–94 Marx’s Capital states that the overthrow of the status quo is inevitable.

  1962 Michael Oakeshott upholds the importa
nce of tradition in public institutions.

  In 1790, British statesman and political theorist Edmund Burke wrote one of the first and most cogent criticisms of the revolution in France, which had begun the previous year. His pamphlet, entitled “Reflections on the French Revolution”, suggested that the passions of individuals should not be allowed to dictate political judgments.

  When the revolution began, Burke had been surprised by it, but not overtly critical. He was shocked by the ferocity of the insurgents, but admired their revolutionary spirit – much as he had admired the American revolutionaries in their quarrel with the English crown. By the time Burke was writing his pamphlet, the revolution had gathered momentum. Food was scarce, and rumours abounded that the king and aristocrats were set to overthrow the Third Estate (the rebellious people). Peasants rose up against their ruling lords, who – in fear for their lives – granted them their freedom through the Declaration of the Rights of Man and of the Citizen. This affirmed that all people had “natural rights” to liberty, property, and security, and to resist oppression.

 

‹ Prev