Book Read Free

Henry Sidgwick- Eye of the Universe

Page 117

by Bart Schultz


  State has a right to prevent a railway from being made through his grounds. Still,

  P: IJD

  cB.xml

  CY/Schultz

  

  February , 

  :

  Colors

  

  compulsory deprivation should be avoided as far as possible, even where it may

  seem abstractly justifiable, on account of the violent resentment that it is likely to cause. (EP )

  And with that, Part I of the Elements comes to an inconclusive close.

  Sidgwick returns to the topic only one more time, briefly, in the chapter on

  “Federal and Other Composite States.” There he reiterates his conviction

  that the mother country must take a hand in regulating relations between

  colonists and aborigines, since the “greater impartiality that may be rea-

  sonably attributed to the home government seems to render it generally

  desirable that the management of the aborigines should not be regarded as

  an ‘internal affair’ of the colony, so long as there is any serious danger of a

  conflict of races or persecution of the inferior race” (EP ). More alarm-

  ingly, however, he also adds some further discussion of the case “where

  the manual labour can never be in the main supplied by the superior race:

  since here the composite character of the population must be regarded as

  permanent unless the races blend.”

  To a society so constituted the governmental structure sketched in the preceding

  chapters is prima facie unsuited: but the extent and nature of the modifications that should be introduced into it must vary very much with the degree of civilisation actually reached by the inferior race, and its apparent capacity for further

  improvement. It will be difficult to prevent a simple oligarchy of the superior race

  from being tyrannical: on the other hand, it seems a desperate resource to give

  equality of electoral privileges to members of the inferior race while admittedly

  unfit to control the operations of government, in the mere hope that experience

  may in time educate them up to a tolerable degree of fitness. So long as the com-

  posite society presents this dilemma, it will probably conduce to its wellbeing as

  a whole that the colony should remain a dependency; so that, even where the

  business of government is mainly left in the hands of the colonists, the control of

  the central government may prevent or mitigate any palpable oppression of the

  inferior race. (EP )

  What can be said on behalf of Sidgwick’s treatment of these ques-

  tions, with all its dismal, disturbing talk of “lower” races and “higher”

  grades of civilization? Against the overwhelming tide of neo-Darwinian

  racism, he holds out somewhat, with an agnostic claim that no seriously

  “debasing” inherent racial differences have been demonstrated scientifi-

  cally, and thinks assimilation possible. Against the overwhelming realities

  of British imperial expansion, he urges that actual spiritual expansion may

  P: IJD

  cB.xml

  CY/Schultz

  

  February , 

  :

  

  Henry Sidgwick: Eye of the Universe

  not necessarily take the form of extended or enduring empire, and that

  although colonization is often a good thing, the rights of semicivilised

  and aboriginal peoples must be protected – especially from the less-than-

  impartial colonists themselves. Despite his warm feelings about the spread

  of his “higher” civilization, he favors the cosmopolitan ideal and clearly

  hopes for more extensive and effective international law and custom to reg-

  ulate all such relations and to help avoid war. His anti-Machiavellianism

  and belief in external and internal sanctions and suasion for enhancing

  world peace would thus appear to circumscribe – subject to utilitarian

  calculation – any imperialistic ventures that the energetic “good people”

  might take on. Indeed, Sidgwick recognizes how abysmally cruel the treat-

  ment of native populations has been, by the “civilised” states, even when

  statesmen were well-intentioned, and he thinks of denying independence

  as in part a measure to ensure that the exploitation by the colonists is

  not perpetuated. And against any educational program that would merely

  underwrite the inferior social and economic position of the “lower races,”

  he demands full educational opportunity to share in the benefits of “civil-

  isation” – the “better religion” and “truer science,” as he elliptically puts

  it. Again, colonial rule, in Sidgwick’s eyes, might advance the general hap-

  piness of humanity, gradually undermining the prescientific superstitions

  and institutions – such as slavery – that have contributed only to human

  misery (not to mention the subjection of women).

  On the other side, of course, is the breathtaking fatuity with which

  Sidgwick designates unfamiliar peoples “lower” or “semi-civilised” or

  “savage,” with perfect insouciance consigning their ways of life to ex-

  tinction. How, given his own skeptical cast of mind and distance from

  spiritual or political orthodoxy, could he have been so unreflectively Eu-

  rocentric, so easily forgiving of what in other contexts he immediately

  recognised as the phenomenon of missionaries rushing out to preach

  things they did not know? And what did it mean, in practice, to be

  so warmly appreciative of the greater impartiality of the home gov-

  ernments, so that their benevolence was linked to maintaining British

  dependencies? “Spiritual expansion” sounds deeply suspicious, even when

  Sidgwick fails, in his all-too-evasive way, to give it much concrete content.

  Moreover, just how lenient was he willing to be about lapses in interna-

  tional duty or comity, when it came to “the duty” of spiritual expansion?

  Was this like Greek love? And what, concretely, did he have in mind

  when referring to such things as the different capacities for manual labor

  P: IJD

  cB.xml

  CY/Schultz

  

  February , 

  :

  Colors

  

  and the possibility of “race degradation”? How did he construct racial

  difference?

  The frustrating feature of Sidgwick’s writings on this score is his ab-

  stract way of describing the issues, the way in which he intentionally tries

  to steer clear of too much concrete political reference, the better to foster

  agreement on principle. Just which peoples did he suppose to be “savage”

  and which “semi-civilised”? What was his list of the future cases where

  the colonists were unlikely to engage in manual labor? What did he mean

  by “race,” and which races did he think would be conquered or fused, and

  which endure? Precisely why was Europe bound to “overcome” Chinese

  civilization?

  Clearly, a great deal of what Sidgwick said about aborigines – like a great

&nb
sp; deal of what he said about the lower classes – derived from his impressions

  of the United States, Australia, South Africa, India, and New Zealand, and

  his impressions of these countries were based entirely on indirect sources,

  chiefly novels and a few select academic works, mostly those of his friends

  and colleagues. As mentioned earlier, Bryce’s American Commonwealth was

  another such work. It is worth dwelling on Bryce’s book at length, given

  Sidgwick’s intimate acquaintance with and high regard for it. Bryce was,

  of course, one of the old cohort, part of the group of academic liberals

  and friends – including Sidgwick, Green, and Symonds – who had toured

  Europe together back in the early sixties, arguing religion, philosophy,

  and politics at every turn. He had accompanied Sidgwick on his fateful

  trip to Italy, was a frequent houseguest, and a most welcome source of

  political gossip. He became not only an influential academic, holding the

  Regius Professorship of Civil Law at Oxford from  until , but

  also a dedicated and conscientious public servant – the  Bryce Com-

  mission on Secondary Education, which urged “a comprehensive central

  authority to formulate policy and the constitution of local authorities to

  administer secondary education,” was of the first importance for pushing

  ahead the improved secondary education that would undergird the im-

  provement of higher education. A longtime Liberal MP, he was invited

  to serve on the India Council (but declined), though he did serve as chief

  secretary to Ireland under Campbell-Bannerman, and as ambassador to

  the United States, not to mention as president of the American Political

  Science Association. An absolutely inveterate traveler, Bryce had experi-

  enced firsthand not only the United States, which he knew quite well, but

  also Canada, Australia, Egypt, South Africa, India, and any number of

  P: IJD

  cB.xml

  CY/Schultz

  

  February , 

  :

  

  Henry Sidgwick: Eye of the Universe

  other lands, in addition to the Eurocentric circuit to which Sidgwick had

  limited himself. He wrote about most of the places he visited, and it would

  not be stretching matters to say that he served as Sidgwick’s “competent

  authority” in chief when it came to factual information on the past and

  present possessions of the British Empire. Both Sidgwick and Bryce, in

  the nineties, would be viewed as remnants of the academic liberals of the

  sixties. Both in due course had become members of the Synthetic Society,

  with Sidgwick regarding his friend as in effect a fellow Apostolic inquirer,

  one with whom he could share his excitement over developments in para-

  psychology. And again, Sidgwick had followed Bryce in insisting on the

  importance of the historical and comparative methods; he thought the

  American Commonwealth a “great work.”

  Sadly, Bryce was also a veritable fund of the offensive racial stereotypes

  characteristic of the late Victorian era, and often these come through with

  special clarity in his discussions of African Americans. Thus, a number

  of key passages in his chapter on the “Present and Future of the Negro,”

  in the American Commonwealth, yield a series of perfectly idiotic claims

  concerning both African and Native American civilizations. Summing up

  the “character and gifts of the Negro,” he writes:

  He is by nature affectionate, docile, pliable, submissive, and in these respects most unlike the Red Indian, whose conspicuous traits are pride and a certain dogged

  inflexibility. He is seldom cruel or vindictive – which the Indian often is – nor

  is he prone to violence, except when spurred by lust or drink. His intelligence

  is rather quick than solid; and though not wanting in a sort of shrewdness, he

  shows the childishness as well as the lack of self-control which belongs to the

  primitive peoples. A nature highly impressionable, emotional, and unstable is in

  him appropriately accompanied by a love of music, while for art he has – unlike

  the Red Indian – no taste or turn whatever. Such talent as he has runs to words;

  he learns languages easily and speaks fluently, but shows no capacity for abstract

  thinking, for scientific inquiry, or for any kind of invention. It is, however, not

  so conspicuously on the intellectual side that his weakness lies, as in the sphere

  of will and action. Having neither foresight nor ‘roundsight,’ he is heedless and

  unthrifty, easily elated and depressed, with little tenacity of purpose, and but a

  feeble wish to better his condition. Sloth, like that into which the Negroes of the

  Antilles have sunk, cannot be generally charged upon the American coloured man,

  partly perhaps because the climate is less enervating and nature less bountiful.

  Although not so steady a workman as is the white, he is less troublesome to his

  employers, because less disposed to strike. It is by his toil that a large part of the

  P: IJD

  cB.xml

  CY/Schultz

  

  February , 

  :

  Colors

  

  cotton, rice, and sugar crop of the South is now raised. But anyone who knows

  the laborious ryot or coolies of the East Indies is struck by the difference between

  a race on which ages of patient industry have left their stamp and the volatile

  children of Africa.

  It was, he argues emphatically, a mistake, an excess of the American fa-

  naticism about identifying citizenship and voting, to have precipitously

  granted Negros the vote in , when generations of slavery had rendered

  them totally unfit to exercise it effectively.

  Bryce goes on to consider the ways in which schools, churches, litera-

  ture, industry, and business are “moulding the Negro,” and his conclusions

  are less than optimistic. He thinks that there “is something pathetic in the

  eagerness of the Negroes, parents, young people, and children, to obtain

  instruction. They seem to think that the want of it is what keeps them be-

  low the whites.” And as for religion, “Among the Negroes, it took a highly

  emotional and sensational form, in which there was little apprehension

  of doctrine and still less of virtue, while physical excitement constantly

  passed into ecstasy, hysterics, and the other phenomena which accom-

  pany what are called in America camp meetings.” Furthermore, in some

  of “the pure Negro districts further south,” there have “been relapses

  into the Obeah rites and serpent worship of African heathendom. How

  far this has gone no one can say. There are parts of the lower Mississippi

  valley as little explored, so far as the mental and moral condition of the

  masses is concerned, as are the banks of the Congo and the Benué.”

  Bryce also suggests that the former slaves have witnessed an “increase

  of insanity, marked since emancipation, and probably attributable to the

  increased facili
ties which freedom has given for obtaining liquor, and to

  the stress which independence and education have imposed on the unde-

  veloped brain of a backward race.” And he also buys into white fears of

  black criminality and sexuality, noting “the large amount of crime. Most

  of it is petty crime, chiefly thefts of hogs and poultry, but there are also a

  good many crimes against women.”

  Furthermore, because the “most potent agency in the progress of the

  humbler and more ignorant sections of a community has always been their

  intercourse with those who are more advanced,” and as this presupposes

  the absence of “race repulsion” and the possibility of intermarriage, the

  American Negro faces special problems: “The day of his liberation was

  also the day when the whites began to shun intercourse with him, and when

  P: IJD

  cB.xml

  CY/Schultz

  

  February , 

  :

  

  Henry Sidgwick: Eye of the Universe

  opinion began to condemn, not merely regular marriage with a person of

  colour, for that had been always forbidden, but even an illict union.” The

  problem of lynching has become serious, rendering the whites cruel and

  lawless and the “docile Negroes” increasingly distrustful of their former

  masters.

  Bryce recognizes that the problem of the color line in America is in

  many ways unique, “a new one in history.” The “relations of the ruling

  and subject races of Europe and Asia supply no parallel to it.” Thus,

  In all such cases . . . though one race or religion may be for the moment dominant, there is no necessary or permanent distinction between them; and there is, if the

  religious difficulty can be overcome, a possibility of intermarriage. Other cases

  may be suggested where a fusion is improbable, as between the British and the

  natives in India, or the colonists and the natives in South Africa. But the European

  rulers of India are a mere handful in comparison with the natives, nor do they settle in India so as to form a part of its permanent population. In New Zealand, the

 

‹ Prev